Jump to content

Aristoxenus

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Aristoxenus of Tarentum)
A modern imagining of the appearance of Aristoxenus.

Aristoxenus of Tarentum (Greek: Ἀριστόξενος ὁ Ταραντῖνος; born c. 375, fl. 335 BC) was a Greek Peripatetic philosopher, and a pupil of Aristotle. Most of his writings, which dealt with philosophy, ethics and music, have been lost, but one musical treatise, Elements of Harmony (Greek: Ἁρμονικὰ στοιχεῖα; Latin: Elementa harmonica), survives incomplete, as well as some fragments concerning rhythm and meter. The Elements is the chief source of our knowledge of ancient Greek music.[1]

Life

[edit]

Aristoxenus was born at Tarentum (in modern-day Apulia, southern Italy) in Magna Graecia, and was the son of a learned musician named Spintharus (otherwise Mnesias).[2] He learned music from his father, and having then been instructed by Lamprus of Erythrae and Xenophilus the Pythagorean, he finally became a pupil of Aristotle,[3] whom he appears to have rivaled in the variety of his studies.

According to the Suda,[2] he heaped insults on Aristotle after his death, because Aristotle had designated Theophrastus as the next head of the Peripatetic school, a position which Aristoxenus himself had coveted, having achieved great distinction as a pupil of Aristotle. This story is, however, contradicted by Aristocles, who asserts that he only ever mentioned Aristotle with the greatest respect. Nothing is known of his life after the time of Aristotle's departure, apart from a comment in Elementa Harmonica concerning his works.[4][5]

Overview of his works

[edit]

His writings were said to have consisted of four hundred and fifty-three books,[2] and dealt with philosophy, ethics and music. Although his final years were in the Peripatetic school, and he hoped to succeed Aristotle on his death, Aristoxenus was strongly influenced by Pythagoreanism, and was only a follower of Aristotle in so far as Aristotle was a follower of Plato and Pythagoras. Thus, as Gibson tells us: "the various philosophical influences"[6](pp ...)[page needed] on Aristoxenus included growing up in the profoundly Pythagorean city of Taras (Tarentum), home also of the two Pythagoreans Archytas and Philolaus, and his father's (Pythagorean) musical background, which he inculcated into his son. Gibson tells us that, after the influence of his father:

The second important influence on Aristoxenos' development was Pythagoreanism: Born in Tarentum, the city in which both Archytas and Philolaos had lived, it can be seen that the extended period of time that Aristoxenus spent in a Pythagorean environment made an indelible impact on the subject matter of his writings. Such titles as "Pythagorou bios", "Peri Pythaorou kai ton guorimon autou" and "Peri tou Pythagorikou biou" indicate Aristoxenus' interest in the society. Furthermore, his works on education show evidence of Pythagorean influence, particularly in their tendency towards conservatism. Most importantly, speculation on the structure of music had its origin in a Pythagorean environment. Its focus was on the numerical relationship between notes and, at its furthest stretch, developed into a comparison between musical, mathematical and cosmological structures.[6](pp 3–4)

However, Aristoxenus disagreed with earlier Pythagorean musical theory in several respects, building on their work with ideas of his own. The only work of his that has come down to us is the three books of the Elements of Harmony, an incomplete musical treatise. Aristoxenus' theory had an empirical tendency; in music he held that the notes of the scale are to be judged, not as earlier Pythagoreans had believed, by mathematical ratio, but by the ear.[7] Vitruvius in his De architectura[8] paraphrases the writings of Aristoxenus on music. His ideas were responded to and developed by some later theorists such as Archestratus, and his place in the methodological debate between rationalists and empiricists was commented upon by such writers as Ptolemais of Cyrene.

The Pythagorean theory that the soul is a 'harmony' of the four elements composing the body, and therefore mortal ("nothing at all," in the words of Cicero[9]), was ascribed to Aristoxenus (fr. 118–121 Wehrli) and Dicaearchus. This theory is comparable to the one offered by Simmias in Plato's Phaedo.

Elementa harmonica

[edit]

In his Elements of Harmony (also Harmonics), Aristoxenus attempted a complete and systematic exposition of music. The first book contains an explanation of the genera of Greek music, and also of their species; this is followed by some general definitions of terms, particularly those of sound, interval, and system.[10] In the second book Aristoxenus divides music into seven parts, which he takes to be: the genera, intervals, sounds, systems, tones or modes, mutations, and melopoeia.[10] The remainder of the work is taken up with a discussion of the many parts of music according to the order which he had himself prescribed.[10]

While it is often held among modern scholars that Aristoxenus rejected the opinion of the Pythagoreans that arithmetic rules were the ultimate judge of intervals and that in every system there must be found a mathematical coincidence before such a system can be said to be harmonic,[10] Aristoxenus made extensive use of arithmetic terminology, notably to define varieties of semitones and dieses in his descriptions of the various genera.[11]

In his second book he asserted that "by the hearing we judge of the magnitude of an interval, and by the understanding we consider its many powers."[10] And further he wrote, "that the nature of melody is best discovered by the perception of sense, and is retained by memory; and that there is no other way of arriving at the knowledge of music;" and though, he wrote, "others affirm that it is by the study of instruments that we attain this knowledge;" this, he wrote, is talking wildly, "for just as it is not necessary for him who writes an Iambic to attend to the arithmetical proportions of the feet of which it is composed, so it is not necessary for him who writes a Phrygian song to attend to the ratios of the sounds proper thereto."[10] However, this should not be construed as meaning that he postulated a simplistic system of harmony resembling that of modern twelve tone theory, and especially not an equally tempered system. As he urges us to consider, "(a)fter all, with which of the people who argue about the shades of the genera should one agree? Not everyone looks to the same division when tuning the chromatic or the enharmonic, so why should the note a ditone from mesé be called lichanos rather than a small amount higher?"[12]

It is sometimes claimed that the nature of Aristoxenus' scales and genera deviated sharply from his predecessors. That Aristoxenus used a model for creating scales based upon the notion of a topos, or range of pitch location,[13] is fact, but there is no reason to believe that he alone set this precedent as he himself does not make this claim. Indeed, the idea of unfixed pitch locations that cover certain ranges, the limits of which may be defined by fixed points, is a notion that was popular until the modern fixation upon fixed pitch systems, as is indicated by Baroque theoretical systems of pitch and intonation. Another way of stating this, however perhaps less accurate, is that instead of using discrete ratios to place intervals, he used continuously variable quantities.

The postulation that this resulted in the structuring of his tetrachords and the resulting scales having 'other' qualities of consonance[14] is one that can only be accounted for by the recourse to often repeated inconsistencies amongst his interpreters and modern confirmation bias in favour of simplified twelve tone theories. Aristoxenus himself held that "... two things must not be overlooked: First, that many people have mistakenly supposed us to be saying that a tone can be divided into three equal parts in a melody. They made this mistake because they did not realise that it is one thing to employ the third part of a tone, and another to divide a tone into three parts and sing all three. Secondly we accept that from a purely abstract point of view there is no least interval."[15]

In book three Aristoxenus goes on to describe twenty eight laws of melodic succession, which are of great interest to those concerned with classical Greek melodic structure.[16]

On rhythmics and metrics

[edit]
Papyrus Oxyrhynchus 9 is a fragment of the "Ruthmica Stoicheia"

Part of the second book of a work on rhythmics and metrics, Elementa rhythmica, is preserved in medieval manuscript tradition.

Aristoxenus was also the author of a work On the Primary Duration (chronos).

A five-column fragment of a treatise on meter (P. Oxy. 9) was published in Grenfell and Hunt's Oxyrhynchus Papyri, vol. 1 (1898) and is probably by Aristoxenus."2687".[17]

Other works

[edit]

The edition of Wehrli presents the surviving evidence for works with the following titles (not including several fragments of uncertain origin):

  • Life of Pythagoras ( Πυθαγόρου βίος ): fr. 11 Wehrli
  • On Pythagoras and his pupils ( Περὶ Πυθαγόρου καὶ τῶν γνωρίμων αὐτοῦ ): fr. 14 Wehrli
  • On the Pythagorean life ( Περὶ τοῦ Πυθαγορικοῦ βίου ): fr. 31 Wehrli
  • Pythagorean maxims or Pythagorean negations ( Πυθαγορικαὶ ἀποφάσεις ): fr. 34 Wehrli
  • Educational customs or Rules of education ( Παιδευτικοὶ νόμοι ): fr. 42–43 Wehrli
  • Political laws ( Πολιτικοὶ νόμοι ): fr. 44–45 Wehrli
  • Mantinean character ( Μαντινέων ἔθη ): fr. 45, I, lines 1–9 Wehrli
  • Praise of Mantineans ( Μαντινέων ἐγκώμιον ): fr. 45, I, lines 10–12 Wehrli
  • Life of Archytas ( Ἀρχύτα βίος ): fr. 47–50 Wehrli
  • Life of Socrates ( Σωκράτους βίος ): fr. 54 Wehrli
  • Life of Plato ( Πλάτωνος βίος ): fr. 64 Wehrli
  • On tonoi ( Περὶ τόνων ): a brief quotation in Porphyry's commentary on Ptolemy's Harmonics, p. 78 Düring (not edited by Wehrli)
  • On music ( Περὶ μουσικῆς ): fr. 80, 82, 89 Wehrli
  • On listening to music or Lecture course on music ( Μουσικὴ ἀκρόασις ): fr. 90 Wehrli
  • On Praxidamas ( Πραξιδαμάντεια ): fr. 91 Wehrli
  • On melodic composition or On music in lyric poetry ( Περὶ μελοποιίας ): fr. 93 Wehrli
  • On musical instruments ( Περὶ ὀργάνων ): fr. 94–95, 102 Wehrli
  • On aulos ( Περὶ αὐλῶν ): fr. 96 Wehrli
  • On auletes ( Περὶ αὐλητῶν ): fr. 100 Wehrli
  • On the boring of aulos ( Περὶ αὐλῶν τρήσεως ): fr. 101 Wehrli
  • On choruses ( Περὶ χορῶν ): fr. 103 Wehrli
  • On tragic dancing ( Περὶ τραγικῆς ὀρχήσεως ): fr. 104–106 Wehrli
  • Comparisons of dances ( Συγκρίσεις ): fr. 109 Wehrli
  • On tragic poets ( Περὶ τραγῳδοποιῶν ): fr. 113 Wehrli
  • Life of Telestes ( Τελέστου βίος ): fr. 117 Wehrli (according to whom this Telestes is the dithyrambic poet)
  • Miscellaneous table talk or Sympotic miscellany ( Σύμμικτα συμποτικά ): fr. 124 Wehrli
  • Notes or Memorabilia ( Ὑπομνήματα ), Historical notes (Ἱστορικὰ ὑπομνήματα), Brief notes ( Κατὰ βραχὺ ὑπομνήματα ), Miscellaneous notes ( Σύμμικτα ὑπομνήματα ), Random jottings ( Τὰ σποράδην ): fr. 128–132, 139 Wehrli

Editions and translations

[edit]
  • Barker, Andrew (1989). Greek Musical Writings, vol. 2: Harmonic and Acoustic Theory (Cambridge), pp. 119–89, English translation with introduction and notes, ISBN 0-521-61697-2
  • Macran, Henry Stewart (1902). The Harmonics of Aristoxenus (Oxford), Greek text with English translation and notes (archive.org, Internet Archive)
  • Marquard, Paul (1868). Die harmonischen Fragmente des Aristoxenus (Berlin), Greek text with German translation and commentary (archive.org, Google Books)
  • Pearson, Lionel (1990). Aristoxenus: Elementa rhythmica. The fragment of Book II and the additional evidence for Aristoxenean rhythmic theory (Oxford ), Greek texts with introduction, translation, and commentary, ISBN 0-19-814051-7
  • Wehrli, Fritz (1967). Die Schule des Aristoteles, vol. 2: Aristoxenos, 2nd. ed. (Basel/Stuttgart), Greek text (excluding the harmonic fragments, rhythmic fragments, On the Primary Duration, and On tonoi: see p. 28) with commentary in German
  • Westphal, Rudolf (1883–1893). Aristoxenus von Tarent: Melik und Rhythmik des classischen Hellenenthums, 2 vols. (Leipzig) (vol. 1, vol. 2)
  • Westphal, Rudolf (1861). Die Fragmente und die Lehrsätze der griechischen Rhythmiker (Leipzig), pp. 26–41, Greek text of Elementa rhythmica and On the Primary Duration (Internet Archive)

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ "Aristoxenus of Tarentum". Chambers's Encyclopædia. Vol. 1. London, UK: George Newnes Ltd. 1961. p. 593.
  2. ^ a b c "Aristoxenos". Suda (Aelian ed.). H. A. ii. 11.
  3. ^ Aulus Gellius. [no title cited]. iv. 11.; Marcus Tullius Cicero. Tusculanae Disputationes. i. 18.
  4. ^ Aristocles ap. Eusebius. Praeparatio Evangelica. xv. 2.
  5. ^ Barker, A. (2007). The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1139468626. Retrieved 2015-05-03. [ed.:] No more of his life-history is known ... .
  6. ^ a b Gibson, Sophie (2005). Aristoxenus of Tarentum and the Birth of Musicology. New York, NY: Routledge. ISBN 041597061X.
  7. ^ Chisholm 1911.
  8. ^ Vitruvius, Book V Chapter IV
  9. ^ Marcus Tullius Cicero. Tusculanae Disputationes. 1.22.51, cf. 1.11.24.
  10. ^ a b c d e f Hawkins, John (1868). A General History of the Science and Practice of Music. Vol. 1. pp. 66–67.
  11. ^ Barker 1989, pp. 142–144.
  12. ^ Barker 1989, p. 163.
  13. ^ Barker 1989, p. 140.
  14. ^ John Chalmers, (1993) Divisions of the Tetrachord, Chapter 3, pp. 17–22. Frog Peak Music. ISBN 0-945996-04-7.
  15. ^ Barker 1989, p. 160.
  16. ^ Barker 1989, pp. 170–183.
  17. ^ Grenfell, B. P.; Hunt, A. S. (1898). Oxyrhynchus Papyri I. London. pp. 14–21.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)

References

[edit]

Further reading

[edit]
  • Bélis, Annie (1986). Aristoxène de Tarente et Aristote: le Traité d'harmonique. Paris, Klincksieck.
  • Barker, Andrew (1978). "Hoi Kaloumenoi harmonikoi: The Predecessors of Aristoxenus". Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society. 24: 1–21. doi:10.1017/s0068673500003990.
  • Barker, Andrew (1978). "Music and Perception: A Study in Aristoxenus". Journal of Hellenic Studies. 98: 9–16. doi:10.2307/630189. JSTOR 630189. S2CID 161552153.
  • Bélis, Annie (2001). "Aristoxenus". In Stanley Sadie; John Tyrrell (eds.). The New Grove Dictionary of Music and Musicians. Vol. 1. London: Macmillan Publishers. p. [page needed].{{cite encyclopedia}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  • Crocker, Richard (1966). "Aristoxenus and Greek Mathematics". In LaRue, Jan (ed.). Aspects of Medieval and Renaissance Music. New York: W. W. Norton and Co.
  • Henderson, Isabel (1957). "Ancient Greek Music". In Wellesz, Egon (ed.). Ancient and Oriental Music. The New Oxford History of Music. Vol. 1. London: Oxford University Press.
  • Huffman, Carl A. (ed.) (2011). Aristoxenus of Tarentum. Discussion. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. (RUSCH XVII).
  • Huffman, Carl (2012). Aristoxenus of Tarentum: Texts and Discussions. New Brunswick: Transactions Publications.
  • Levin, Flora (1972). "Synesis in Aristoxenian Theory". Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association. 103: 211–234. doi:10.2307/2935976. JSTOR 2935976.
  • Lippman, Edward (1964). Musical Thought in Ancient Greece. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Rowell, Lewis (1979). "Aristoxenus on Rhythm". Journal of Music Theory. 23 (Spring): 63–79. doi:10.2307/843694. JSTOR 843694.
  • Winnington-Ingram, R. P. (1980). "Aristoxenus". In Stanley Sadie (ed.). The New Grove Dictionary of Music and Musicians. Vol. 1. London: Macmillan Publishers. p. [page needed].{{cite encyclopedia}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
[edit]